by Aaron W . Hughes (Author)
Aaron W. Hughes presents the first major study of dialogue as a Jewish philosophical practice. Examining connections between Jewish philosophy, the literary form in which it is expressed, and the culture in which it is produced, Hughes shows how Jews understood and struggled with their social, religious, and intellectual environments. In this innovative and insightful book, Hughes addresses various themes associated with the literary form of dialogue as well as its philosophical reception: Why did various thinkers choose dialogue? What did it allow them to accomplish? How do the literary features of dialogue construct philosophical argument? As a history of philosophical form, context, and practice, this book will interest scholars and students working at the intersections of religious studies, philosophy, and literature.
Format: Paperback
Pages: 234
Publisher: Indiana University Press
Published: 04 Feb 2008
ISBN 10: 0253219442
ISBN 13: 9780253219442
Book Overview: Jewish philosophy as a dynamic literary, cultural, and social practice
Aaron W. Hughes presents a study of dialogue as a Jewish philosophical practice. Examining connections between Jewish philosophy, the literary form in which it is expressed, and the culture in which it is produced, Hughes shows how Jews understood and struggled with their social, religious, and intellectual environments. He addresses various themes associated with the literary form of dialogue as well as its philosophical
reception: Why did various thinkers choose dialogue? What did it allow
them to accomplish? How do the literary features of dialogue construct philosophical argument? As a history of philosophical form, context, and practice, this book will interest scholars and students working at the intersections of religious studies, philosophy, and literature.Joseph Haberer, Book Editor, SHOFAR, Volume 27, Number 2, Winter 2009
At the beginning of his important new book, The Art of Dialogue in Jewish Philosophy, Aaron Hughes notes that the academic study of Jewish philosophy has traditionally centered on great men ... and their great texts (p. 2). Hughes's work, by contrast, is part of a recent trend in scholarship that seeks to broaden these traditional parameters by examining less important or epigonic thinkers, as well as a wide variety of secondary forms, such as biblical commentaries, sermons, encyclopedias, and polemical works. Thus, Hughes's book takes for its subject the rather neglected genre of the Jewish philosophical dialogue, in which context he looks not only at such major figures as the twelfth-century Spanish poet and critic of philosophy Judah Halevi, the sixteenth-century Italian Renaissance humanist Judah Abravanel, and the eighteenth-century German Enlightenment thinker Moses Mendelssohn, but also at such lesser figures as Shem Tov ibn Falaquera and Isaac Polleqar, both staunch exponents and defenders of the medieval Jewish rationalist tradition active in Spain, the former in the thirteenth century, the latter in the fourteenth. Hughes's focus on the genre of the dialogue leads him to take note of the interplay between the literary features of such works and their more strictly philosophic argumentation, again in contrast to the traditional approach of Wissenschaft des Judentums that placed prime emphasis on ideas, often divorced from specific textual contexts (p. 2). Finally, his emphasis with regard to these dialogues on the subtle exchanges and interactions, sometimes collegial, sometimes adversarial, between their various characters enables Hughes to bring to light not just these dialogues' literary dimensions, but also their oftentimes polemical aspects and their engagement with the burning religious, cultural, and intellectual issues of their day. Hughes's book thus bridges the divide separating the history of philosophy from intellectual history.
The Art of Dialogue in Jewish Philosophy is framed by an introductory chapter, Expanding the Canon of Jewish Philosophy, in which Hughes sets forth the book's main goals (briefly discussed in our opening paragraph) and outlines its contents, and an epilogue, From Dialogue to Dialogic, in which he briefly traces and attempts to account for the uncertain and rather modest fortunes of the Jewish philosophical dialogue in modern times. The body of the book consists of five chapters, each devoted to examining a dialogue--in one case two dialogues--from the five above-mentioned philosophers, beginning with Halevi's Kuzari (1140), then moving on to Falaquera's Epistle of Debate (c. 1250) and Book of the Seeker (1263 [?]), Polleqar's Ezer ha-Dat (c.1350), Abravanel's Dialoghi d'amore (1511-1512 [?]), and concluding with Mendelssohn's Phaedon (1767). In each chapter Hughes follows a similar structure, first situating a particular dialogue in its historical, social and intellectual environments, then proceeding to situate the author of each dialogue against this backdrop, and finally moving to an examination of the particular text in question (p. 24).
Hughes's presentation is clear, thoughtful, and learned, and readers will learn much from it. On the whole, the book is successful in achieving its goals. Certainly Hughes convincingly shows the importance of the Jewish literary dialogue for any comprehensive study of the history of medieval and early modern Jewish philosophy. His analyses of the polemical functions of Falaquera's Epistle of Debate and Polleqar's Ezer ha-Dat are particularly strong, and he skillfully locates these works in the ongoing controversy over the role of philosophy in Judaism in the wake of the writings of Maimonides, with Falaquera representing an earlier stage of the debate, defending philosophy against the criticisms of traditional Talmudists, while Polleqar represents a later stage, defending philosophy against the two-pronged attack of Kabbalists and astrologers. Hughes also makes good on his claim that paying closer attention to the interplay between the literary features of a dialogue and its more strictly philosophic argumentation will lead to a deeper and more accurate philosophic understanding of the work. Thus, in his discussion of Book 2 of Ezer ha-Dat, consisting of a debate between a young, rather radical exponent of philosophy who argues that only philosophy is the source of truth, and an older anti-philosophical, Kabbalistically inclined traditionalist who argues that only religion is the source of truth, Hughes notes that the eminent historian of Jewish philosophy Shlomo Pines sees the young philosopher as a stand-in for the author (p. 193, n. 86), as a result of which Pines ends up attributing radical proto-Spinozistic views to Polleqar. In truth, Hughes points out, a literary analysis of the book indicates that Polleqar sides neither with the young philosopher nor with the old traditionalist, but with the king who appears on the scene to arbitrate the dispute and seeks to harmonize the views of the two antagonists.
The book, however, is not free from weaknesses, and Hughes at times presses his arguments too far. Thus while, as noted above, Hughes skillfully limns the polemical functions of Falaquera's Epistle of Debate and Polleqar's Ezer ha-Dat, his claims regarding the polemical functions of Abravanel's Dialoghi and Mendelssohn's Phaedon carry less conviction. Hughes shows that in the Dialoghi Abravanel develops a Jewish version of the popular Renaissance literary genre known as the tratatto d'amore (treatise on love) (p. 115), while in the Pheadon Mendelssohn articulate[s] the soul's immortality in ways that were completely divorced from contemporaneous theological (i.e., Christian perspectives) (p. 154). He is on shakier ground, however, when he proceeds to argue that the Dialoghi is a Jewish response to some of the decidedly Christocentric features of Renaissance humanism (p. 132) and similarly that the Phaedon is a polemical work designed to demonstrate to a primarily Christian audience that Christianity is not a prerequisite to felicity of the soul after corporeal death (p. 140). Here Hughes places too much weight on what, when all is said and done, are arguments from silence.
Even more problematic is Hughes's claim that the Kuzari should be seen as a polemic against the spiritualist Muslim movement known as Isma`ilism. Hughes correctly points out that the Kuzari argues for the superiority of `amal (action) over niyya (intention), and goes on to maintain that the Isma`ilis argue for a reverse evaluation. Similarly, he correctly points out that Isma`ili texts argue for the superiority of the batin, the inner, esoteric core of religion over its zahir, its outer, exoteric form, and goes on to maintain that the Kuzari argues for a reverse evaluation. But in none of the Isma`ili texts that Hughes cites are the terms `amal and niyya so juxtaposed, and in none of the texts from the Kuzari that Hughes cites are the terms batin and zahir so juxtaposed. Indeed, in the Kuzari 3:73, the rabbinic sage, here clearly a spokesman for Halevi, in discussing problematic rabbinic Aggadot states that they are impossible only according to their zahir, their external sense. By implication they should be understood according to their batin! Here Halevi uses the zahir/batin distinction in an Isma`ili-like manner, though he limits the distinction to problematic rabbinic Aggadot, while the Isma`ilis apply it to religion as a whole. In any event, the matter is more complex than would appear from Hughes's discussion.
Moreover, in places Hughes's literary analysis requires further refinement. Thus, to return to the previous example, while Hughes is correct in asserting that in Book 2 of Ezer ha-Dat, Polleqar sides neither with the young philosopher nor with the old traditionalist, but with the king who appears on the scene and seeks to harmonize the views of the two antagonists, he is incorrect in asserting that the king attempts to harmonize the truths of philosophy and religion (p. 96: emphasis mine). Rather, the king states that philosophy is the source of true knowledge, while religion seeks to straighten [our] deeds, and direct our attention toward good and beautiful works. The clear implication is that religion itself is not a source of truth. In this regard the king sides with the young philosopher. Polleqar appears here to be carefully covering his tracks, giving the impression that the king splits the difference between the young philosopher and the old traditionalist, when in truth he is considerably closer the former. Perhaps, then, Polleqar's position is not that far removed from Spinoza after all! (One difference might be that Polleqar, unlike Spinoza, does not seem to admit the possibility of a purely philosophical ethics, even for philosophers themselves.)
Beyond these reservations regarding the larger issues of Hughes's analyses of the polemical functions of these dialogues and the interplay between their literary features and their more strictly philosophic argumentation, I have some reservations regarding more specific points. Thus, Hughes maintains that Abravanel in the Dialoghi celebrates sensual love as the gateway to cosmic or spiritual love (p. 130). But in the passage that Hughes cites in support of this claim Abravanel celebrates not sensual love, but physical beauty. And while I agree with Hughes that Mendelssohn's synthesis of Judaism and Enlightenment values is fragile, I do not agree with his contention that the Phaedon is a good example of that fragility. Hughes offers two arguments in support of this view. First he notes that in his Hebrew version of the Phaedon, the Sefer ha-Nefesh, Mendelssohn cites liberally from biblical prooftexts. Such citations attest, Hughes goes on to claim, that in that work Mendelssohn... does not hesitate to make appeals to revelation to buttress his claims, something he did not do in the Pheadon (p. 164). Setting to the side the fact that it would obviously be absurd for Socrates in the Phaedon to cite biblical prooftexts, can Mendelssohn's citations of such texts in the Sefer ha-Nefesh be described as appeals to revelation ? Here I would point to a passage in Jerusalem where Mendelssohn states that while scripture certainly contains an inexhaustible treasure of rational truths and religious doctrines, these excellent propositions, in addition to their being purely rational, are presented to us for our consideration without being forced upon our belief. In light of this passage, the biblical prooftexts attesting to the immortality of the soul, cited by Mendelssohn in the Sefer ha-Nefesh, rather than constituting appeals to revelation forced upon our belief, are just examples of scripture's inexhaustible treasure of rational truths... presented to us for our consideration. Second, Hughes cites an excerpt from a letter to Hartwig Wessely in which Mendelssohn seems to apologize for ever having written Phaedon (p. 165).
One would never know from Hughes's description that this letter was written to Wessely thanking him for expressing an interest in translating the Phaedon into Hebrew. In the excerpt cited by Hughes Mendelssohn is describing what he had initially assumed would be the likely reaction of Wessely to the Phaedon. Mendelssohn knew that Wessely was not very philosophically inclined, and he had feared that Wessely might not approve of his having written the Phaedon, deeming the philosophic demonstration of such a fundamental principle of our holy faith as that of the immortality of the soul to be unnecessary, perhaps even dangerous. But in truth, as Mendelssohn goes on to write in a passage not cited by Hughes, in light of Wessely's interest in translating the Phaedon into Hebrew, he now sees that Wessely approves of those who engage in philosophic inquiry, providing they `give heed to the works of the Lord' (cf. Ps. 28:5) in sincerity. Thus, far from apologizing for ever having written Phaedon, Mendelssohn took comfort in the fact that the non-philosophical Wessely, who was well known and highly regarded as an outstanding Hebraist, appeared to approve of the Phaedon. This was an encouraging sign, confirming, in Mendelssohn's view, the solidity--not the fragility--of his synthesis.
It need not be said that the reservations I have raised require further discussion and analysis and that this is not the place for such an undertaking. It also need not be said that none is intended to detract from the importance of Hughes's book, a work which consistently enlightens and informs, even if it does not always convince.Lawrence Kaplan, McGill University, H-Judaic, January 2009
With this work Aaron Hughes has established himself as a prominent member of a new wave of Jewish scholars who... are charting exciting new directions for Jewish philosophy. -Jim Kanaris, McGill University, Studies in Religion / Sci Rel, Vol. 38.1 2009
[R]epresents an important new trend in Jewish philosophy, and moves the field one step closer to a complete social, cultural, and literary history. -James Robinson, University of Chicago Divinity School
Aaron W. Hughes is Associate Professor in the Department of Religious Studies at the University of Calgary, Canada. He is author of The Texture of the Divine: Imagination in Medieval Islamic and Jewish Thought (IUP, 2004).